Skip to content(if available)orjump to list(if available)

How to avoid P hacking

How to avoid P hacking

44 comments

·May 9, 2025

parpfish

I was heavily encouraged to do what would later be called “p-hacking”, but it looked different from what they describe here. This article describes p-hacks for people that aren’t into math/stats. I always ended up p hacking because I was into stats methods.

Somebody would say “here’s an old dataset that didn’t work out, I bet you can use one of those new stats methods you’re always reading about to find a cool effect!”, and then the fishing expedition takes off.

A couple weeks later you show off some cool effects that your new cutting edge results were able to extract from an old, useless dataset.

But instead of saying “that’s good pilot data, let’s see if it holds up with a new experiment”, you’re told “you can publish that! Keep this up and maybe you’ll be lucky enough to get a job someday!”

gwerbret

> Stopping an experiment once you find a significant effect but before you reach your predetermined sample size is classic P hacking.

Although much of the article is basic common sense, and although I'm not a statistician, I had to seriously question the author's understanding of statistics at this point. The predetermined sample size (statistical power) is usually based on an assumption made about the effect size; if the effect size turns out to be much larger than you assumed, then a smaller sample size can be statistically sound.

Clinical trials very frequently do exactly this -- stop before they reach a predetermined sample size -- by design, once certain pre-defined thresholds have been passed. Other than not having to spend extra time and effort, the reasons are at least twofold: first, significant early evidence of futility means you no longer have to waste patients' time; second, early evidence of utility means you can move an effective treatment into practice that much sooner.

A classic example of this was with clinical trials evaluating the effect of circumcision on susceptibility to HIV infection; two separate trials were stopped early when interim analyses showed massive benefits of circumcision [0, 1].

In experimental studies, early evidence of efficacy doesn't mean you stop there, report your results, and go home; the typical approach, if the experiment is adequately powered, is to repeat it (three independent replicates is the informal gold standard).

[0]: https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/17321310/

[1]: https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/16231970/

bjornsing

There are of course statistical methods designed to support early stopping. But I don’t think you can use a regular p-test every day and decide to stop if p < 0.05. That’s something else.

parpfish

In lots of human studies, you can’t just stop at an arbitrary number of participants because you’ve counterbalanced manipulations to decorrelate potential confounders (e.g., which color stimulus is paired with reward, the order of trials).

coolcase

Sounds like a variable cost experiment. Each observation cost x$. Like an A/B split on Google ads. Why keep paying for A when you know B is better already.

nialse

Small samples have more variability than large samples and thus more often show spurious large effects.

rrr_oh_man

Google Optimize used to tell you to let an experiment run for one-two weeks (?), exactly because early strong results tend to not don't hold up in the long run.

-> https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Regression_toward_the_mean

hiddencost

https://commons.m.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:P-hacking_by_early...

The author is absolutely correct. Early stopping is a classic form of p hacking. See attached image for an illustration.

If you want to be rigorous, you can define criterion for early stopping such that it's not, but you require relatively stronger evidence.

Clinical trials that stop early do so typically at predefined times with higher significance thresholds.

ekianjo

There is another reason to keep clinical trials as long as designed. To understand the safety and side effects implications.

neilv

> As any gambler knows, if you roll the dice often enough, eventually you’ll get the result you want by chance alone

You never count your results, when you're sitting at the lab bench, there will be time enough for counting, when the experiments are done.

boulos

Nicely done. Since many folks may not know the original song: https://en.m.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Gambler_(song)

(And TIL, this wasn't original to Kenny Rogers!)

cypherpunks01

Like the old saying goes,

"It is difficult to get a researcher to stop P hacking, when his career depends on his not stopping P hacking."

bjornsing

Yeah that was kind of my feeling too while skimming through this: ”Good luck with that…”

It’s not a knowledge problem. It’s a vales and incentives problem.

spinf97

> Ending the experiment too early

> Running experiments until you get a hit

But if I'm running an experiment how do I know how many time to run it.

pizlonator

The worst part about this:

> Running experiments until you get a hit

Is that it's literally what us software optimization engineers do. We keep writing optimizations until we find one that is a statistically significant speed-up.

Hence we are running experiments until we get a hit.

The only defense I know against this is to have a good perf CI. If your patch seemed like a speed-up before committing, but perf CI doesn't see the speed-up, then you just p-hacked yourself. But that's not even fool proof.

You just have to accept that statistics lie and that you will fool yourself. Prepare accordingly.

starspangled

> Is that it's literally what us software optimization engineers do. We keep writing optimizations until we find one that is a statistically significant speed-up.

I don't think that is what it is saying. It is saying you would write one particular optimization (your hypothesis), and then you would run the experiment (measuring speed-up) multiple times until you see a good number.

It's fine to keep trying more optimizations and use the ones that have a genuine speedup.

Of course the real world is a lot more nuanced -- often times measuring the performance speed up involves hypothesis as well ("Does this change to the allocator improve network packet transmission performance?"), you might find that it does not, but you might run the same change on disk IO tests to see if it helps that case. That is presumably okay too if you're careful.

LegionMammal978

"Multiple times" doesn't have to mean "no modifications". Suppose the software is currently on version A. You think that changing it to a version B might make it more performant, so you implement and profile it. You find no difference, so you figure that your B implementation isn't good enough, and write a slight variation B', perhaps moving around some loops or function calls. If that makes no difference, you keep writing variations B'', B''', B'''', etc., until one of them finally comes out faster than version A. You finally declare that version B (when properly implemented) is better than version A, when you've really just tried a lot more samples.

throwanem

Why is this bad for you? You're optimizing software, not trying to describe reality. Monte Carlo and Drunkard's Walk are fine.

cortesoft

Well, what is the test you are using to measure performance? Maybe the optimizations help performance in some cases and hurts performance in others... your test might not fully match all real world workloads.

analog31

You're churning the user experience for no reason. Maybe constant optimization churn is one of the reasons why UIs are so bad.

throwanem

Perf, though? If a perf optimization changes the UI noticeably other than by making it smoother or otherwise less janky, someone is lying to someone about what "performance" means. Likely though that be, we needn't embarrass ourselves by following the sad example.

No, UIs churn because when they get good and stay that way, PMs start worrying no one will remember what they're for. Cf. 90% of UI changes in iOS since about version 12.

pizlonator

Yeah!

And software ultimately fails at perfect composability. So if you add code that purports to be an optimization then that code most likely makes it harder to add other optimizations.

Not to mention bugs. Security bugs even

jean_lannes

These seem like two different things. Testing many different optimizations is not the same experiment; it's many different experiments. The SE equivalent of the practice being described would be repeatedly benchmarking code without making any changes and reporting results only from the favorable runs.

pizlonator

Doesn’t matter if it’s the same experiment or not.

Say I’m after p<0.05. That means that if I try 40 different purported optimizations that are all actually neutral duds, one of them will seem like a speedup and one of them will seem like a slowdown, on average.

daveFNbuck

That's not p hacking. That's just the nature of p values. P hacking is when you do things to make a particular experiment more likely to show as a success.

bbertelsen

There's another cheeky example of this where you select a pseudo-random seed that makes your result significant. I have a personal seed, I use it in every piece of research that uses random number generation. It keeps me honest!

doubletwoyou

what they’re referring to might be better put as applying a patch once and then running it 500 times until you get a benchmark thats better than baseline for some reason

which is understandably a bit more loony

pizlonator

Nah it could be 20 different patches.

babuloseo

how can I do this in python what modules?

smallmancontrov

It might be below the fold, but it looks like they're missing the most important p-hacking strategy of all: the dogshit null hypothesis. It's very reliable and it's the most common type of p-hacking that I see.

It's easy to create a dogshit null hypotheses by negligence or by "negligence" and it's easy to reject a dogshit null hypothesis by simply collecting enough data as it automatically crumbles on contact with the real world -- that's what makes it dogshit. One might hope that this would be caught by peer review (insist on controls!) but I see enough dogshit null hypotheses roaming around the literature that these hopes are about as realistic as fairy dust. In practice, the dogshit null hypothesis reins supreme, or more precisely it quietly scoots out of the way so that its partner in crime, the dogshit alternative hypothesis, can have an unwarranted moment in the spotlight.

nmca

This would be much better with an example

smallmancontrov

"I ran a t-test on the untreated / treated samples and the difference is significant! The treatment worked!"

...but the data table shows a clear trend over time across both groups because the samples were being irradiated by intense sunlight from a nearby window. The model didn't account for this possibility, so it was rejected, just not because the treatment worked.

That's a relatively trivial example and you can already imagine ways in which it could have occurred innocently and not-so-innocently. Most of the time it isn't so straightforward. The #1 culprit I see is failure to account for some kind of obvious correlation, but the ways in which a null hypothesis can be dogshit are as numerous and subtle as the number of possible statistical modeling mistakes in the universe because they are the same thing.

somenameforme

I think you're more observing an issue with experimental models not challenging a null hypothesis, than with poor null hypotheses themselves. In other words, papers creating experiments that don't actually challenge the hypothesis. There was a major example of this with COVID. A typical way observational studies assessed the efficacy of the vaccines was by looking at outcomes between normalized samples of nonvaccinated and vaccinated individuals who came to the hospital and seeing their overall outcomes. Unvaccinated individuals generally had worse outcomes, so therefore the vaccines must be effective.

This logic was used repeatedly, but it fails to account for numerous obvious biases. For instance unvaccinated people are generally going to be less proactive in seeking medical treatment, and so the average severity of a case that causes them to go to the hospital is going to be substantially greater than for a vaccinated individual, with an expectation of correspondingly worse overall outcomes. It's not like this is some big secret - most papers mentioned this issue (among many others) in the discussion, but ultimately made no effort to control for it.

null

[deleted]

aw1621107

> looks like they're missing the most important p-hacking strategy of all: the dogshit null hypothesis

Would you mind giving an example(s) of such and how it differs from a "good" null hypothesis?

eviks

The irony of the article appearing in the "career" section when following its advice means you'll not have a career

p4ul

If the conclusion is "be transparent", I'm strongly supportive.

And moreover, I would be even more supportive if we found a way to change the incentives for tenure and promotion such that reproducibility was an important factor in how we make decisions about grants, tenure, and promotion.

analog31

Just make it even more cutthroat than it already is. Replacing one hackable incentive system with another will just produce a new set of hacks.

Disclosure: I left academia before I had to worry about any of this.

notpushkin

> You have full access to this article via your institution.

Huh. I’m not on a university connection or anything. Is it just open access?

gregwebs

This is one of the most disturbing articles I have seen related to reproducibility because it seems to imply that scientists don’t already know this.

a_bonobo

As a biologist all the field wants is p < 0.05. What it actually means is unnecessary. It's a hurdle to pass to have another paper on your CV.

shoo

see also: Andrew Gelman's blog

> The problem with p-hacking is not the "hacking," it’s the "p." Or, more precisely, the problem is null hypothesis significance testing, the practice of finding data which reject straw-man hypothesis B, and taking this as evidence in support of preferred model A.

https://statmodeling.stat.columbia.edu/2021/09/30/the-proble...

See also this post from 2014 with a discussion of Confirmationist and falsificationist approaches to reasoning in science: https://statmodeling.stat.columbia.edu/2014/09/05/confirmati...

> I understand falisificationism to be that you take the hypothesis you love, try to understand its implications as deeply as possible, and use these implications to test your model, to make falsifiable predictions. The key is that you’re setting up your own favorite model to be falsified.

> In contrast, the standard research paradigm in social psychology (and elsewhere) seems to be that the researcher has a favorite hypothesis A. But, rather than trying to set up hypothesis A for falsification, the researcher picks a null hypothesis B to falsify and thus represent as evidence in favor of A.

> As I said above, this has little to do with p-values or Bayes; rather, it’s about the attitude of trying to falsify the null hypothesis B rather than trying to trying to falsify the researcher’s hypothesis A.

> Take Daryl Bem, for example. His hypothesis A is that ESP exists. But does he try to make falsifiable predictions, predictions for which, if they happen, his hypothesis A is falsified? No, he gathers data in order to falsify hypothesis B, which is someone else’s hypothesis. To me, a research program is confirmationalist, not falsificationist, if the researchers are never trying to set up their own hypotheses for falsification.

> That might be ok—maybe a confirmationalist approach is fine, I’m sure that lots of important things have been learned in this way. But I think we should label it for what it is.

See also: Andrew Gelman and Eric Loken's 2014 "garden of forking paths" paper: https://sites.stat.columbia.edu/gelman/research/unpublished/...